HerodotusThe Seventh, Eighth, & Ninth Books with Introduction and CommentaryMachine readable text


Herodotus
By Reginald Walter Macan




Perseus Documents Collection Table of Contents



PREFACE

INTRODUCTION
   Unity of the last three Books of Herodotus
   Justification of the existing subdivisions
   Characteristic and Analysis of Bk. 7
   Characteristic and Analysis of Bk. 8
   Characteristic and Analysis of Bk. 9
   Is the work of Herodotus incomplete, or unfinished?
   General considerations in support of the priority of Bks. 7, 8, 9
   Particular passages favourable to the priority of Bks. 7, 8, 9
   Marks of successive Redactions in Bks. 7, 8, 9
   The Sources: analysis inconclusive
   Defects and Merits of Herodotus historicus as exhibited in Bks. 7, 8, 9
   The false and the true estimates of Herodotus and his work

THE TEXT


Funded by The Annenberg CPB/Project

INTRODUCTION

  [sect. 11]

Defects and Merits of Herodotus historicus as exhibited in Bks. 7, 8, 9

To the analysis of the Sources naturally succeeds the estimate of the historian's power of dealing with them, and generally the merits and defects of his mind and method, as exhibited in the work, or the portion of the work, here immediately under review. No ancient historian was really a scientific and critical historian, as these terms are nowadays understood: Thucydides himself will not stand untarnished the tests of the modern analyst. Ancient historians take liberties in the interests of art, of charm, of literature, which modern historiography has discarded, and modern students would not appreciate if revived or imitated. Nevertheless, ancient historians are critical and competent in widely varying degrees, and their works, tried by their own best standards, as by ours, deserve careful and discriminating appreciation. Herodotus has a unique character of his own, which nowhere shows to greater advantage than in these Books. To an incomparable style, combined with a happy empiricism which allows, or seems to allow, every party to a suit to tell its own story, he adds a critical effort or rational conscience, not always advertised, and an honesty, or open-mindedness, which outshines the malignity of his Sources. If he seeks after signs and wonders, and prefers proverbial wisdom and bons mots to metaphysic, his work is possibly none the worse a mirror of the times for that. His rationale of political action, his grasp of the operations of war, are seldom adequate to our way of thinking; yet he often enables us to correct or to supplement his own account from the context. His chronology nowhere else so nearly responds to modern requirements as in the last three Books; the topographical conditions of the story of the war are remarkably [p. lxxvii] well satisfied, while incidentally a large contribution is made to the materials of Comparative Jurisprudence, or the early history of Institutions. Exaggerations, inconsistencies, fictions abound in his pages; yet this liberty of prophesying, as he practises it, carries to some extent its own remedy with it, and detracts surprisingly little from the purely historical results to be obtained. A more detailed discussion of the points just formulated will go far to justify the favourable verdict.

(i.) That liberty which Herodotus, in common with most ancient historians, carried with him into his composition, may be most significantly tested by an examination of the speeches and dialogues plentifully introduced into the last three Books of the work.95 From the purely critical point of view perhaps the best to be said for them is that they are not quite all equally unauthentic and fictitious. In some cases there may be a genuine reminiscence of words spoken on the given occasion; yet, even in passages apparently the most plausible, the language has taken on so strong an Herodotean colour that we cannot see in Herodotus a mere reporter: he has arranged the matter for publication, and the full copyright is his. Thersander of Orchomenos doubtless told to Herodotus the anecdote of his experiences at the banquet of Attaginos, but the conversation of Thersander with his Persian convive has a native Herodotean ring, which makes it, in its present form, unmistakeably the author's; unless, indeed, Herodotus learnt a good deal of his own philosophy from the Boiotian.96 Even less convincing is the conversation between Dikaios and Demaratos in the Thriasian plain on the eve of the battle of Salamis, for the substance of which Herodotus is nevertheless at some pains to specify his source.97 Few if any of the remaining dialogues and conversations have an alleged authority; not seldom the circumstances and conditions in which the speeches are introduced, no less than their substance or contents, prohibit their acceptance. The situation is frequently private and confidential, the interlocutors Persians, and the conversation of course ex hypothesi conducted in Persian though reported in Greek. Improbabilities, inconsequences, even absurdities, occur in the conversations and [p. lxxviii] speeches, which it is much more natural to ascribe to the reporter, or inventor, than to the hypothetical interlocutors. It will be hard for any one to gainsay the free creative action of the historian in regard to the deliberations of Xerxes and his councillors. The two speeches of Mardonios, the three speeches of Artabanos, the four speeches of Xerxes, which preface the final decision for war, can hardly be more authentic than the dreams and apparitions which the historian employs to overcome the king's reluctance to decide for war.98 The dialogue of Xerxes and Artabanos at Abydos is but a vehicle for Greek sentiment and ethics concerning the life of man, for a criticism on the Persian conduct of the war, placed in the lips of these dramatis personae without any apparent historical justification.99 Some readers may be tempted to ascribe a higher degree of probability to the three conversations reported between Xerxes and Demaratos, in view of this or that special source connected with the exiled Spartan king, and presumably accessible to Herodotus.100 Such a source might help doubtless to explain the prominence of Demaratos in the historian's pages (where he succeeds Artabanos in the character of Choregos, or Sage); but the substance of the supposed conversations discredits their historical claim. The first and second interviews are transparent devices for expounding in dramatic form Hellenic, and especially Lakedaimonian, traits and qualities, the better to explain and to glorify the defence of Greece; the third is a no less transparent device for conveying a criticism upon the Persian strategy or plan of campaign: here the Persian admiral, Achaimenes, appears as tritagonist, in order to provide a spokesman for the alternative actually followed, and to explain why the Persians failed to adopt a course of action only too likely to have been successful. Probably differences of opinion existed in the king's suite upon the conduct of operations; courses recommended by Greek exiles, who knew their own countrymen, might, if adopted, have furthered the king's cause; but a good deal of the criticism, thus dramatically represented, may be the result of afterthought, on both sides, coming to the historian ready-made, and owing to him little more than its dramatic form and [p. lxxix] hypostatization. Even the prominence of Artemisia in the King's councils before and after the battle of Salamis cannot be construed into an authentication of the speeches, reported for these occasions101 ; and the remarks fathered on Xerxes at Tempe,102 though doubtless illustrative of the despotic mind, are as fictitious in this connexion as his conversations with Pythios,103 which subserve the same general purpose.104

On the Greek side, where assuredly there was no lack of speechifying in real life, Herodotus to a great extent has avoided reporting set speeches, or contented himself with the oblique oration in reporting them. Given cases make all the better impression for this abstinence, the feeling produced being that the historian reports the point and marrow of arguments which were used, must have been used, or might have been used, upon the occasion. So with the speeches at Athens,105 at the Isthmos,106 before the war: so with the Parainesis of Themistokles to the Epibatai on the very morning of the battle of Salamis,107 or the discussion with Eurybiades thereafter.108 Where Herodotus breaks into direct oration professing to give the ipsissima verba of his speakers, the reports become more and more incredible. The largest set piece of this kind on the Greek side is the interview between the Greek ambassadors and Gelon, the tyrant of Syracuse, where the speeches are no doubt the vehicles for a good deal of candid criticism, very much in place in the historian's pages, under one form or another, but not at all likely to have been uttered by the given speakers upon the given occasion.109 The debates of the Greek Strategoi before Salamis are reported partly in oblique, partly in direct oration; and it may safely be said that the former passages have more verisimilitude than the latter.110 The principal set speech of Themistokles contains, indeed, an admirable argumentation, but the arguments must have been used much earlier than the point at which they occur in the historian's narrative111 ; while the interview and dialogue between Themistokles and Aristeides is transparent [p. lxxx] fiction.112 The discussion in the council of war at Andros,113 like the discussion in the council of war at Samos,114 both reported in oblique oration, contain at least veritable points of dispute, doubtless at issue and debated on the occasion; but the larger set speeches, of Alexander, the Spartans, the Athenians, on the question of an Athenian union with the Persian, are quite unacceptable in their actual form.115 More plausible are the speeches, briefly reported, in Lakedaimon soon afterwards116 ; but the great orations of the Tegeatai and Athenians on the battlefield of Plataia, whatever the historical incident that lurks hid in the situation, are plainly out of place and time.117 To what category must the short oration of the Korkyraians before Xerxes be assigned which is reported ipsissimis verbis albeit ex hypothesi never delivered?118 To the same category as the message of Themistokles to Xerxes, addressed by the lips of a messenger warranted to keep silence in regard to his trust even in the extremity of torture!119 Many speeches, reported by Herodotus, are reducible to messages on the battle-field, or diplomatic pourparlers, where the substance is plainly or plausibly historical, and the form is comparatively unimportant; others dwindle to the dimensions and purpose of bons mots (ἔπη εὖ εἰρημένα), with an immortal right to exist, whatever their unauthenticity!120

Doubtless for the contents of many of the speeches reproduced in his pages Herodotus had what he believed to be sufficient justification in the reports or traditions that had reached him orally, or in writing. In other cases, doubtless, he has more or less consciously followed the principle formulated by Thucydides, to put into the mouth of each speaker the sentiments (and ideas) proper to the occasion. This principle is, however, one no longer consistent with the practice of the historical muse: it marks a method which even the most rhetorical historiography of our days will not adopt, despite the examples of Herodotus and Thucydides, of Livy and Tacitus. It is a method confined in our literature to the historical novelist, so called. In some of the cases above cited it is employed by Herodotus with a freedom which astonishes us even in the pages of an ancient author; and such action makes it very difficult for us to suppose [p. lxxxi] that this liberty of creation, or of report, was confined to words, and debarred from events and conduct, or that where speeches are transparent fiction narrative is all hard fact.

(ii.) One matter of fact, into which fiction has certainly made way, consists in the numbering of the forces of Xerxes. The full results are, indeed, presented by Herodotus, not as bare facts traditionally or authoritatively guaranteed, but in part at least as products of argument and computation: the data are themselves manifestly unsound, and the initial mistake naturally generates a self-multiplying aberration.121 The final result is a miscalculation rather than a fable, and attaints the author's judgement rather than the character of his Sources. Yet there was plainly that in his Sources to start him upon this road to ruin; and the instance shows at once the licence of his Greek authorities, and the inability of Herodotus to control or to amend it. One hundred and seventy myriads of fighting men is the total which Herodotus accepts at starting as the figure for the infantry of Xerxes massed and numbered at Doriskos, with eighty thousand added for the cavalry.122 Such forces the Persian king might conceivably have levied from his vast empire; but such forces he could not have taken with him into Greece, nor supported had he taken them thither. The figure is, however, only an estimate, based upon an incredible anecdote, and not a total reached by a summation of various items for the various component parts of the army. Herodotus, indeed, is not content with the given figures; but, far from seeking to diminish them, he is shortly attempting to increase them, and succeeds, to his own satisfaction, in raising the total of the king's forces by land to upwards of two million fighting men. The numbers for the fleet are not perhaps so extravagant, though a total of upwards of half a million men at arms is a manifest exaggeration. Misjudgement and absurdity reach a climax in the proposal to double the figures throughout in order to make allowance for attendants and followers, raising the total of the men led by Xerxes as far as Thermopylai and the Thessalian shore to upwards of five millions and a quarter. This passage is of the utmost importance for a just estimate of Herodotus' competence as a military historian. His figures and his computation set conditions of time and space [p. lxxxii] at defiance: the initial device, by which the total for the infantry was obtained at Doriskos, is itself an absurdity. If other figures for fleets and forces on both sides are more moderate and sane, that cannot expunge the deliberate and express misjudgement to which Herodotus is committed in this instance. The total of the Persian fleet (raised by the European contingent to 1327 vessels) Herodotus reduces by storms and captures before Salamis to about 600 vessels; but he supposes these losses to have been fully compensated by the contingents of Karystos, Andros, Tenos, and other Nesiotes: a manifest absurdity.123 Such arithmetical irresponsibility, in the face of physical and historical conditions, is not to be condoned by the observation that the motives of exaggeration in both directions are transparent enough. The defect of science here is a defect of art likewise, and almost of common sense. Ars est celare artem. It may be questioned whether any one has ever taken these figures and computations for truth except Herodotus himself. The deliberate effort to make the most of the hosts of Xerxes has drawn attention to the physical conditions and the recorded facts of the case, which alike disprove the historian's reckoning. There are no two pages in the whole work of Herodotus more fatal to his claims as a sober historian than the pages devoted to these systematic and elaborate computations. Herodotus is dealing seriously from first to last in this business; it is not an exaggerated jest nor an ironical satire: that is the worst of it! Solvuntur risu tabulae! The thing is ridiculous, and neither the rivers that failed,124 nor the surpassing stature and beauty of Xerxes,125 invented apparently ad hoc, can save Herodotus from bankruptcy on this account.

(iii.) Naturally computation is not the only particular in which Herodotus breaks down as an historian of military affairs. Passing over here his description of the arms and accoutrements of the vast host, his account of its march with the king at its head leaves much to be desired, even on his own showing. Despite its colossal size, the host remained, if we are to credit Herodotus, a chaotic mob, until it reached Doriskos.126 Again, [p. lxxxiii] though we may detect in his records evidence that the army was organized in three corps or columns, and advanced in that order, it is evidence of which he himself seems unconscious, and the arrangement is only predicated by him of one short stage on the route.127 Again, although in one place he indicates that the Persian strategy treated, so long as possible, fleet and army as indissoluble,128 he shows practically no consciousness of this clue in his own narrative of the two campaigns, but treats the movements of the fleets and armies, on both sides, as wholly independent, though accidentally synchronous, series of operations; and while he has incidentally enabled us to relate the battles of Thermopylai and Artemision to each other, he has left the relations of the movements of the Greek fleet in 479 B.C. to the operations on land, a matter of pure speculation. His accounts of individual battles break up for the most part into successions of disconnected episodes. His diary of the fighting in front of Plataia must be pronounced on the whole his chef d'uvre in this kind; yet it is replete with obscurities and improbabilities, and indicates very little conception, on the writer's part, or that of his informants, of the strategic and tactical conditions involved. It may be that materials for an adequate and reasoned record of the Persian war hardly existed in the time of Herodotus, or that, for all his merits and goodwill, he was not just the right man to collect and to digest them; but neither plea alters the actual quality of the narrative in question. The best that can be said of his military essays is that they preserve an outline of events, which might otherwise have been wanting, and contain scattered hints showing the actual war to have been conducted on intelligible and intelligent principles. These hints justify the endless attempts on the part of Herodotus' followers and commentators to reconstruct with more or less success the probable plans of the two belligerents, and the actual contour of the various operations by sea and by land, in the course of the Persian war.

(iv.) Conditions and limitations, which precluded success in the attempt to give a true history of the war, have not enabled Herodotus to present an adequate or accurate version of the policies of the states or statesmen whose acts and advices he had to record. Policy is a less technical concern than strategy and [p. lxxxiv] tactics; yet states fare little better in the pages of Herodotus than fleets and armies. It is hardly to be reckoned a serious fault if he represents the policy of Persia as ultimately dependent on a despot's caprice; yet his own pages teem with proofs of the inevitable character of the Persian war.129 Neither the action nor the inaction of Sparta is traced to any clear motives, or objects of policy, in these Books; and, as it happens, an important development of Spartan policy in relation to Athens and the Persian question is reported, in the sixth Book, in terms which reduce the account to a mere anecdote; yet among all Greek states the policy of Sparta is at all times the most easily explained.130 The conduct of Athens is throughout represented in the heroic terms accepted from the Attic or philo-Athenian sources131 ; the material and political interests which Athens had at stake, and in especial the definite object to resist a tyrannic restoration under Persian auspices, is barely indicated, or but unconsciously suggested. The policy of the Medizing states is, perhaps, more successfully adumbrated than the policy of those who chose the better part132 : the divisions of Thessaly,133 the feud of Phokis,134 the anti-Atticism of Thebes,135 the anti-Lakonism of Argos,136 are verae causae, most clearly expressed in the cases of Phokis and of Argos. Over the political attitudes and sympathies of Makedon and of Delphi a glamour had been thrown, we cannot but suspect, in the light of later events and interests, which Herodotus has accepted somewhat too credulously at its own valuation. Yet on the whole the political motives of the various states named are historical problems not difficult of solution in and from his records, although the truth in regard to the political action of Delphi and of Makedon in particular may never be quite clearly recovered. It is in dealing with the behavious and motives of individuals that his sympathies, or his sources, betray Herodotus into something like superficial injustice. The attitude and action of Alexander [p. lxxxv] of Makedon have been reported probably from sources deeply coloured by the political results of the Persian war. The record of Themistokles does little justice to the political objects and abilities, or even the patriotism, of that statesman, and Herodotus has failedhas not attemptedto get behind the traditions and anecdotes which dated from his fall, or were the outcome of the hostilities that helped to fell him. The political action of Gelon in relation to the Persian and national question has been obscured in the Herodotean record by the general Hellenic antipathy to tyrants, though fortunately in this case later and local knowledge has led Herodotus to supplement the general tradition, current in Athens or Sparta, with a special variant, which proves at once good history and good politics, more than justifying the non-appearance of Gelon at Salamis, justifying also the doubt whether his co-operation was ever invited at all. The character of Xerxes, as a politician, has been reduced, in the conflicting tradition preserved by Herodotus, to that of a paradoxical puppet, partly swayed by supernatural interventions and agencies driving him on to his doom, partly led by evil councillors more astute and ambitious than himself, partly the creature of his own capricious and ungovernable passions. That there was no real precedent for such a portrait it would be rash to affirm; but it is safe to say that the particular motives assigned for many of the King's undertakings and actions are unduly prejudiced, and that where good reasons were forthcoming, Herodotus did ill so often to prefer the worse reason for the conduct of Xerxes.137

(v.) It is, in short, not unfair to say that Herodotus was primarily neither a military nor a political historian, and does not always show to advantage beside a Thucydides, a Polybios, a Caesar, or even a Tacitus. Herodotus prefers the concrete to the abstract, the particular to the universal, the anecdote, the episode, the bon mot, the gnome, to the reasoned description of military movements, or the conscious rationale of political events. Even his record of the second Persian war, much the most closely connected and best sustained achievement in his logography, teems with sportive items.138 Such things are not history, though they may be, if rightly authenticated, a part of the materials out of [p. lxxxvi] which history is to be made, or at least to be made agreeable. In a sense, indeed, they are better than history, they are mostly too good to be true; but in general they are at once either too artful or too artless to rank as good historical evidences. In the one case they betray the moral, and in the other case the malignity, which has been at the making of them; or at best they drop out of serious account as pure sports of the humorist, or raconteur.

(vi.) Again, the record of the Persian war as told by Herodotus suffers detriment, from the strictly historical point of view, by the too ready admission of the marvellous, the miraculous, the special intervention of the other world, in one shape or another. To justify Herodotus from this charge, in a certain sense, is easy enough. Granted that Xerxes was not hounded on by divinely ordered dreams and apparitions to carry out the pre-ordained purpose of Heaven in the invasion of Greece139 : granted that the deliverance of Delphi was unaccompanied by special apparitions and miracles140 : waiving the reported interventions, omens, portents, that cluster round Salamis and its story141 : rationalizing the telepathic Phem at Mykale, and its reputed synchronism with the victory of Plataia142 : yet still, it may be said, Herodotus had failed for all time to represent a notable and perfectly historical feature in the traditions of the war, aye, in the souls of the victors themselves, had he omitted to reproduce these irrational elements in the story as it reached him from the age of faith. These elements are features in the story, because such elements, the same in kind if not in amount and prominence, were factors in the life of Greece in the fifth century. Oracles, dreams, portents, with their interpretation, counted for something, not insignificant, in the actions of living men and women, and in the policy of states, in a pre-metaphysical age. And what fault could be found with Herodotus if he but reported the cases where the oracle was appealed, and helped to determine action, or failed to do so, as might be; if he but recorded marvels, or supposed marvels, or any other religious excuse, as actual motives of action, and even of policy? The suspicion is unavoidable that, strong as was the belief in the direct intervention of [p. lxxxvii] gods and heroes in human affairs, important as was the rle played by oracles, divination, the interpretation of portents, dreams, and so forth, in real life, yet all these things nevertheless played less part in men's actions and fortune than the logography of Herodotus would lead us to suppose. The charge is rather that, owing to an idiosyncrasy, a personal penchant for such things, he has given them an undue prominence in his narrative to the exclusion of more genuinely historical elements; he has preferred a supranaturalistic story, or version of a story, to a more natural one; he has transfused his whole conception and representation of the course of affairs so as to bring it into agreement with a somewhat thin and antiquated view of the action of the God in History; and, both in what he inserts and in what he omits, in the form he has given to his materials, or the forms he has accepted and preferred, the bold miracle has too often taken the place of the better reason.143 It may be some compensation to us that by this very miscarriage and shortcoming Herodotus all the more fully represents the popular mind of his age and people, and so becomes, in a fresh application, historical in our eyes; but this consolation is tantamount to admitting that, in the first instance, he presents to us an imperfectly historical mind, and represents an imperfectly historical age, or rather the less instructed side of an age, which was already in all its leading minds essentially scientific.

(vii.) Of the worst charge against the good faith of an historian Herodotus stands acquitted: personal bias, personal ill-will, should never have been alleged against him. As formulated in the pages of Plutarch's tract de Malignitate Herodoti this charge, a monument of critical incompetence, collapses upon the Boiotian critic's own pate. A good deal of malignity is, indeed, preserved in the pages of Herodotus, but it is there as evidence, for the most part, of the surpassing candour and simplicity of the writer's own mind. Kretans were not the only liars in Greece: Greeks all told stories at each other's expense, Athens to the discredit of Sparta, of Korinth, of Thebes, each of which doubtless returned the compliment with interest: oligarch maligned democrat, and democrat maligned oligarch, and both united to blacken the tyrant's fame: feuds of clan with clan. [p. lxxxviii] and rivalries of man with man, gave constant vogue to the worse report and the worse interpretation of each other's actions. It was a part of the price paid by the Greeks for their enfranchisement.144 All this carnival of calumny is reflected in the pages of Herodotus, thanks to his direct reproduction of the local version, the partisan story, the rival's anecdote, the apologist's retort. But there is little or no malice in his own private judgements, nor is a malign spirit consistent with the general tone of his work. That Herodotus betrays no political or personal preferences it would be too much to assert: such a miracle of impartiality would be more or less than man and than Herodotus; but he errs by excess rather than by defect of admiration. His two worst offences in this connexion are to have taken too easily the current Athenian transfiguration of Athens, and the current Athenian denigrations of Themistokles. For the rest, Herodotus preserves somewhat more than a benevolent neutrality. Who can say that he does less than justice to Lakedaimon, if he reproduces too faithfully one Athenian jibe at Sparta's honour?145 Or to Korinth, if he reports the Athenian scandal, with the universally received dmenti in immediate juxtaposition?146 Or to Argos, for whose conduct he apologizes with, perhaps, half an eye to the Attic question?147 Or to Thebes, whose medism was past whitewashing, even though the account of the Thebans at Thermopylai is one of the weakest spots in the historian's armour?148 Yet there is little or nothing in all this, and in the lesser cases which might be cited, to convict Herodotus in his own person of ill-will to any man or state in Hellas.149 That he does no injustice to the Barbarian has often enough been pointed out150 : that not even Plutarch's captious tract alleged against him.

(viii.) Herodotus' own reflexions are seldom profound, and never ill-natured.151 His very empiricism refutes the charge of [p. lxxxix] ill-will.152 His method of letting people tell their own story, instead of rationalizing or reducing all his conflicting materials to a self-consistent prcis, enables his readers to compare one account with another for themselves, and to correct at times the version preferred by the historian in the light of one reported on principle. Not indeed that Herodotus quite fulfils his own formula. He has not been at sufficient pains always to collect information from every source legitimately concerned. It is certainly strange, and a little unfortunate, that the campaign of Plataia should be so largely drawn from Athenian tradition, and throughout Herodotus is too much at the mercy of his Athenian authorities. Yet even here the very transparency of the medium supplies its own corrective, and the absence of conscious or deliberate special pleading on the historian's part enables his readers to improve on his position. This observation holds good even of the stories of the nautical and military operations: we may venture to rationalize them just because the historian has done little or nothing himself in that direction. If, on the whole or in parts, we claim to understand the course of events better than our best authority, it is not so much that we correct and supplement his record largely from other sources, but rather that his record so largely supplies its own corrective, in the conflict of evidences reported, and the manifest animus of much reproduced bona fide by the reporter. Such reconstruction can be but hypothetical, and of course depends for its acceptance upon appeal to still verifiable facts in the physical conditions, and in the nature of man; but it is not thereby discredited as illegitimate, and its verisimilitude is due, in the last resort, to the simple good faith of the first report.

(ix.) The navet of Herodotus must not, however, be exaggerated; the presence of a critical and a rationalistic tendency in his work cannot be denied. He has himself exercised to some extent a judgement, if not in the selection, at least in the evaluation of his sources, rejecting stories as untrue, or improbable, which he still thinks it his duty to report, entering his own opinion and verdict in some disputed cases formally for what it is worth, and incidentally or implicitly forcing on his audience [p. xc] a certain reading of the facts, a certain rationale of the merely empirical order of phenomena, or the merely empirical roll of witnesses. In some cases this element of reflexion, when segregated and envisaged on its own merits, leaves very little to be desired. No one will claim for Herodotus the rank of a philosophic thinker; yet the rationale which he gives, in one way or another, sometimes speaking in his own person, sometimes by the lips of his dramatis personae, sometimes it may be in the mere way of narrative, of the Greek victory over the Persians, is all but complete. On the Persian side the unmanageable size and numbers of the hosts153 ; disregard of sound policy and errors in the actual plans of campaign154 ; division of interests, rivalry and quarrels among the leaders, and in the command155 ; division of interests and lack of coherence in the fighting forces156 ; positive inferiority in equipment, armour, skill, discipline, training157 : what more could be required to explain the issue? On the Greek side the contrary and the complement of all these: the advantage in actual material and military equipment158 ; the advantage in skill, in discipline, in leadership, in intelligence; union159 ; the advantage in manhood and in moral160 ; the vast superiority of the cause.161 Yet Herodotus does not escape a certain inconsequence between his clear perception of the secondary causes accountable for the Greek victory, and his strong, desire to make the most of the danger, and to magnify the result, as a great and wonderful work, not to be explained by any merely human actions or considerations. In the end he is not content, short of the invocation of his highest categories for human experience. In his mind the victory is due, immediately and ultimately, to the direct interposition of the gods and heroes, the higher individual wills which rule the world, and to the supreme laws of all human life and fortune.162 Religiously speaking the discomfiture of Xerxes, the salvation of Greece, are ascribed to the jealousy excited in the god, Zeus, by the pride and power of the man, Xerxes163 ; or [p. xci] ethically expressed, to the sure nemesis which lies in wait for the high and mighty things of this world, to the certain if slow corruption which is the lot of mortality, to the law that happiness is not for man, and human life at best a sorrowful thing.164 Doubtless this moral has led Herodotus to portray in Xerxes the character which deserves the judgement, to emphasize in the traditions those traits and anecdotes which accord with the foregone conclusion; but even here his method, careless of inconsistencies, has redeemed his work; showing that the historic Xerxes was not the mere despot, proud and capricious, cruel and cowardly, vicious and well-nigh insane, as too much of the record implies, but that his actions were guided at least in some degree by the intelligible motives of a politician, and the reasonable feelings of a man.

Nor can it be said that Herodotus' empirical method of narrating stories, or his meternpirical doctrines of Divine vengeance and of mortal doom, have much diminished his political sagacity and fairness, where there is a call for their application. His view of the service of Athens, and of the importance of that service to the cause of Greece, though insufficiently qualified by any clear statement of the great interests Athens had at stake, is nevertheless on its positive side a judgement in which the modern world must acquiesce. His perception of the separatist feelings underlying the action and policy of the Peloponnesian states is clear enough. His problematical interpretation of the conduct of Sparta at a critical moment is ambiguous only in form165 ; and his explanation of the final determination to co-operate loyally with Athens is none the less his own for being put into dramatic form.166 Throughout, Herodotus must have credit for reporting with understanding the political wisdom and sagacity of his heroes or dramatis personae, even where he is not actually fathering on them his own reflexions; and the application of this principle proves that, although his express judgements on political affairs appear at times strangely superficial, yet this current superficiality is consistent with a high degree of political shrewdness upon occasion. Even his anecdotes, though doubtless often apocryphal, may be regarded as the deliberately chosen vehicles for a good deal of sound sense, and political or ethical philosophy. Such [p. xcii] parables as the Crown of Virtue,167 the Dinner la Perse,168 the Answer of Kyros,169 have each as clear a moral as the fable of Persuasion and Necessity170 put into the mouth of Themistokles to adorn a solemn historic occasion. The reflective element in Herodotus' work is far larger than appears at first sight, owing to the skilful means which he has adopted to render it more easily digestible. It is the very dotage of criticism to suppose that Herodotus is unconscious of his own devices, or incapable of the wit and wisdom which he has made his own; he himself must be credited with most of the reflexion which we find in his pages, whether it take the form of express judgements delivered ex cathedra by the historian himself, or be conveyed dramatically by speakers in the course of his narrative, or wear the still more lively and insidious guise of an anecdote en passant, or a bon mot, recorded for what it is worth. It is perhaps not too much to say of these elements in the last three Books that they bear more directly on the general theme, and cohere more closely with the proper texture of the story, than do similar elements in other sections of the work; and this observation also tends to the general credit of this volume of Logoi, whether regarded as a permanent contribution to history, in the strictest sense of the term, or merely as a literary achievement calculated to give pleasure to readers, or listeners, in moments of leisure.

(x.) The geographical deposit is another element in which the last three Books of Herodotus approach more nearly to the standards of sound historiography than any other considerable section of the work. The comparative fulness and accuracy of the geography is partly incidental to the subject, like the advantage which the narrative of Thucydides gains from being concerned with relatively well-known landscapes, and scenes amenable to methods of simple inspection. Not that Herodotus even in these Books is a scientific geographer, or free from empirical errors; but, defects and errors notwithstanding, the contribution which he makes incidentally to the cartography of the Aigaian area, of ancient Greece, of parts of Asia, especially minor Asia, is not inconsiderablea positive contribution, as matters stand for us, quite independent of the question, how far the geographical data in his work are the result of his own researches, and how [p. xciii] far the geography has come to him ready-made by his predecessors, or involved in the narrative, as found in his Sources.171

(xi.) The chronology of the war deserves appreciation on similar lines: scientific, or even approximately systematic, it is not; yet nowhere in the work of Herodotus is the chronology so good as in the last three Books. Here too the advantage is inherent in the subject, the story of a short and recent war of invasion: but what of that? The admission but emphasizes the historical quality of the record. The exact period of the war, the succession of the seasons, the temporal sequence of events, some well-remembered intervals, some approximate synchronisms, even the Ephemerides or diaries of important sections of the story, are presented for all time in the pages of Herodotus. Many weighty and interesting problems of chronology are indeed left doubtful; some apparently precise indications prove, on closer scrutiny, ambiguous; but still the narrative as a whole emerges, relatively speaking, a chronological triumph for the Father of History. His great disciple, and rival, Thucydides, seems to have done little new in this matter except to systematize and apply to a more extensive and amenable subject the method evolved by Herodotus in the stories of the Persian war.172

(xii.) Finally, the last three Books of Herodotus are not lacking in materials for students of Comparative Jurisprudence, of Ancient Law and Early Institutions, of Folk-lore, even if the deposit under this head be less rich than in the Books of foreign travel and research, notably the second and the fourth. A careful analysis of the Logoi here in question will soon discover a very considerable contribution to the institutional history not merely of the Greeks,173 in particular of Sparta174 and of [p. xciv] Athens,175 but in a lesser degree of the Persians,176 and even of the outer Barbarians.177 Primitive Culture parades in many guises through the Army and Navy Lists of the Empire; systems of military tactics and command are seen on both sides in operation; forms of government, monarchy, oligarchy, democracy, are put to the test; principles and practices of international custom are formulated, or illustrated; religious cults and ideas start from every page; ethical standards and sentiments abound in evidence; the condition of the arts and sciences is exhibited; the story of the war becomes a survey of mankind. All these items of anthropology are, indeed, no more immune to criticism than the express contributions of military and political history; but they gain in credit and in use by the very fact that their publication was not the main purpose of the argument. The incidental fact, which occurs so to speak in an alien stratum, is historically all the more acceptable for being unnecessary to the object immediately in view.